Marsilio Ficino: Platonic Theology. Vol. 1: Books I–IV.
English translation by Michael J. B. Allen with John Warden.
Latin text edited by James Hankins with William Bowen.
The I Tatti Renaissance Library, Vol. 2.
Harvard University Press, 2001.
0674003454.
xvii + 342 pp.
Now that I have sort-of caught up with the I Tatti Renaissance Library
(except for the volumes published this year, which I haven't bought yet), I figured
it's a good time to go back to the only ITRL volumes that I skipped so far,
namely Ficino's Platonic Theology. It came out in 6 volumes
early in the series (2001–6, one volume each year) and I bought them
as they appeared, but didn't read them at the time. Actually I tried reading
a little of volume 1, following the arguments earnestly, like you would in a
mathematical textbook, and keeping notes about everything I thought wrong
about them — the wishful thinking, the unwarranted assumptions, the wooly-minded
and ill-definded concepts, etc. etc. etc. — but soon I gave this pursuit up
as futile. One could, in principle, get through the whole six-volume set
in that manner, but what would be the point? I clearly was neither enjoying
it nor learning anything in the process.
So I laid the Platonic
Theology aside and went on with the other volumes in the ITRL series,
and it was not until reaching Ficino's commentaries on Plato (ITRL vols. 34, 51–2)
that I found a way to make reading Neoplatonic mumbo-jumbo palatable to me,
by approaching it more as a very odd sort of fantasy fiction than as something
that is supposed to be true and logically sound (see one of my posts
from back then). And it is armed with this approach, plus with what little
I've managed to learn about Neoplatonism from Ficino's other works in the
ITRL series (and from the little I've read of Plotinus, Dionysius and for that matter
Plato himself) that I now went back to his Platonic Theology.
[P.S. I wondered whether I should make one blog post per volume, or just a single
long post for all six volumes. Since the six volumes constitute a single work
and I read them one after another without interruption, I figure it's more
convenient to make it into a single post, even if it's a bit longer than usual.]
Book I
Ficino introduces a five-level hierarchy of what he calls “essences”:
body, quality, soul, angel, God. This is clearly very similar to the hierarchy
that we saw in his commentary on the Parmenides (matter, form, soul, intellect,
the One), but now with more explicitly christian rather than pagan terminology.
In fact I'm not sure if there are any really meaningful differences between the two
hierarchies at all. For example, at the lowest level one has body and the other
has matter. But Ficino says here that “body is made up of matter and of
quantity”, matter is only “extended in space” and “quantity
is nothing but the extension of matter” (1.2.1), so it's hard for me to see
much of a difference between body and matter. It's hard to resist the feeling
that his concept of matter is very different than what we have in physics nowadays,
and that I'd probably be less prone to misunderstand him if he used some other word
for it, even if he had to make up an entirely new one.
Next above body he has quality, which he defines as “all form which appears,
divided up, in body” (1.3.1). I'm not sure what to make of the word “form”
here. Until now I thought it, when used in the context of Plato's philosophy and the
like, “form” was simply the same thing as “idea”, but borrowed
from Latin rather than Greek; and that both are more or less the same as the native
English word “shape”; and I thought of these Platonic ideas as some kind
of mental abstractions, e.g. you have the ‘idea of a dog’ that exists in the Platonic ‘higher’ or ‘intelligible’ world and is a kind of template
of the dogs that we know and love in our ordinary ‘lower’ or ‘sensible’
world (i.e. the world that is accessible to our senses and not only to our intellect).
But how to square this with Ficino's description of quality as a kind of form?
Well, perhaps it is not his use of “form” but his use of “quality”
that I misunderstand here. I thought of quality as ‘surface features’
like ‘being white’ or ‘being hot’ and the like; but maybe
it's more than that. Ficino often describes matter as a “formless
substrate” and the like (1.3.8, 1.3.15), which suggests it's something
undifferentiated that is all alike everywhere, and it is only when quality gives
it a certain shape (i.e. form) that some matter here may constitute a dog and some
matter somewhere else may constitute a horse and so on.
In constructing the higher levels of his hierarchy, Ficino proceeds largely
by wishful thinking and vigorous gesticulation. Quality, he says, cannot come
from something equal to itself (i.e. another quality) or from something lower
(e.g. matter), but from something higher (1.3.9), and since quality is extended (divided)
in matter, this higher form must be indivisible and incorporeal (1.3.10).
Such an incorporeal, indivisible form is what conveys unity to the otherwise
divisible object, so that it can be one object at all (1.3.21).
Another wishful argument: surely, he says, just like the human mind can climb
from lower to higher and more abstract concepts, a similar ascent must also exist
in the universe itself, from lower to higher forms (1.3.11). Anyway, by such
‘arguments’ he arrives at the (rational) soul, an indivisible form
which gives bodies their qualities (1.3.25).
He writes a good deal about motion, but from the way he uses this word I got
the impression that he took “motion” to include every kind of change.
We would say that a body of e.g. a living person changes all the time, but
to him the body is just formless matter so he says that qualities change all
the time (1.4.1), and since it is the soul that conveys qualities to the body,
the soul itself is at least partly ‘in motion’. But partly
it is ‘motionless’ — its essence doesn't change (1.4.3), by which I guess he means
things like: even if the body of a living person is constantly changing, nevertheless
it remains in some sense the same body of the same person, and this comes from
the unchanging part of the soul.
Again proceeding by wishful thinking, since soul is partly in motion and partly motionless,
he figures that there must be something completely motionless above it.
There seems to be an unwritten Neoplatonic axiom at play here: if A is more perfect than B,
and B exists, then A must also exist :] Motion means change over time,
and something is more perfect if it's timeless (eternal) and unchanging (1.5.2).
Thus he arrives at a higher form which is motionless itself but can set
the souls below it into motion; and unlike soul it is entirely free of matter (1.5.10).
He mentions the term “mind” for such forms, used by ancient philosophers
(not only Platonists — he also gives an example from Aristotle; 1.5.10),
but “the Hebrews and later philosophers [. . .] called these
minds angels and messengers” (1.5.11), and so he adopts the term angel —
rather confusing at first sight, in my opinion. Since they are not constrained by matter,
there can be a lot more different kinds of angels than of souls, and Ficino makes
some reference to the angelic
hierarchy such as we know it from Dionysius and similar authors (1.5.14).
Another unwritten Neoplatonic axiom seems to be that if A differs from B in two aspects,
then there must exist an intermediate thing between them that differs from each of them
in only one aspect :) We already saw that the soul is (partly) mobile
and there is also a certain plurality about it (as it moves (i.e. changes) from one
thing to another); and angel is motionless, but it cannot be motionless unity
because it would then differ from the soul in two ways instead of just one;
so it must be motionless plurality, and there must be some sort of motionless unity
above it — and this, of course, is God (1.6.2). I suppose that all arguments
for the existence of god are more or less ridiculous, but I still couldn't help
that this particular one was more ridiculous than usual.
For Ficino, God is largely synonymous with truth and goodness, and he has a few
interesting paragraphs explaining the relations between soul, angel and God
(1.6.5–7). He gives an analogy (1.6.5): the eye perceives light; if your
eye grew so that your whole body would be one big eye, it would perceive more light,
but would still be distinct from light itself. Similarly,
your mind is a part of the soul that perceives truth (= God); but an angel is all mind,
and thus perceives more truth; but it is still distinct from truth itself
(“the mind needs truth, but truth does not need mind”; God is
“clearest truth [. . .] the light seeing itself”, 1.6.6).
The function of the soul is “to provide vital motion” to living
beings; the function of the mind is “to order by means of forms” (1.6.7),
and thus its power extends farther than that of the soul (because every living being
has a form but some non-living things have a form too). And similarly, since God is
goodness, its power extends farther than that of the mind, because even matter
(which is formless) “desires” the good. (You might wonder how
formless, mindlesss matter can ‘desire’ anything. I can only suppose
that when he says ‘desires’, that's simply sloppy phrasing for
something like ‘has the potential for’.)
Book II
This longish book is about the various properties of God, the fifth essence
discovered in the previous book. Much of this stuff is so abstract that I had
little real idea what to do with it.
The early parts of this book mostly try to demonstrate that there is exactly
one god, as you would expect given that Ficino is a monotheist. He starts by reiterating that
truth, goodness and unity are the same thing (and are also the same thing as God),
but I was very unimpressed by the handwaving by which he purports to demonstrate
this (2.1.1). His arguments that there is nothing higher than these three things
(or rather this one thing) were a bit more reasonable; for instance, if there
existed some higher principle than unity, then unity itself would consist of a part
that participates in that higher principle and a part that doesn't, so it wouldn't
be unity at all (2.1.2).
He similarly argues that there cannot be several distinct but somehow equivalent
highest principles (i.e. gods), because then they would have to have something in
common (since they are equivalent), and then that common aspect would be an even
higher principle (2.2.2). He also rejects dualism, the idea that there might be
two gods, a purely good one and a purely evil one: the purely evil one cannot
exist since existence is something good and if he existed, he wouldn't be purely evil
(2.2.10). This sounds technically
correct, but I can't help feeling somehow cheated
when I encounter arguments like that :]
There's also a chapter about how there cannot exist an infinite succession of
gods one above the other (2.3), but I had the feeling that his arguments here
ultimately come down to little more than a vague discomfort about infinite sequences
with no clear beginning. He keeps insisting that there must be a first cause of
things, otherwise there would be flux and chaos everywhere (2.3.3–4).
Ficino says that weakness comes from dispersion, but strength from unity;
thus, since god is perfect unity, his power is infinite (2.4.1) — in modern
terms we might say that god is a singularity :P He has another argument:
we see that god keeps moving the universe regularly over such long periods without
any changes, so clearly his power is inexhaustible, and hence infinite (2.4.4).
He ‘proves’ that god is everlasting by a hilarious technicality.
God, we saw, was truth; and if truth had a beginning then, before that beginning,
it would still be true that there will be a beginning; so truth would exist before
its beginning, which is absurd; and you can likewise show that truth has no end,
so it is everlasting (2.5.1). He uses an interesting term that was new to me: sempiternal,
which apparently means everlasting in the sense of having an infinite duration,
whereas eternal can be used by philosophers to mean things which
exist outside time altogether (wiktionary).
God is omnipresent, partly for simple reasons such as because he's the ultimate
cause of everything (and thus in a sense present in all things; 2.6.1), or because
being everywhere is a good thing and thus god as the ultimate good cannot lack that
(2.6.2). But he also has a more interesting argument: god is everywhere because
“He Himself is ‘the everywhere’ which contains itself and
everything else” (2.6.5).
God is the ultimate source of all being; he exists through himself, other
things exist through him (2.7.3). An interesting argument for this is that a composite
thing exists through the harmony of its parts, so the only thing that can exist through
itself is a purely unitary thing (i.e. god, who is unity itself); 2.7.3.
Since the existence of all things depends on god, he can be said to “preserve”
everything (2.7.6).
God acts not by deliberation or choice, but by his very being, easily and
effortlessly, much like e.g. the Sun gives off light naturally by its being and
not by some sort of deliberate effort (2.8.1).
Understanding is a good thing and god is the ultimate good, so obviously
he has understanding (2.9.2); he understands himself perfectly and thus, since
he is the cause of all other things, he also understands all other things (2.9.5).
“In God, being and understanding are completely identical” and both
are infinite (2.10.3).
Occasionally Ficino uses arguments that remind me a little of modern-day creationists:
“the amazing order of the world could not come about through chance devoid of order”,
so its “form must necessarily exist in the understanding of its maker” (2.11.7);
thus, in a sense, the forms of all things are in god. He creates those other things
not by understanding alone, but by exerting his will (2.12.1); but then in him, willing
and understanding are identical anyway (2.12.5). He is “the fount of reason”
and thus does not act by chance, and so it could be said that his will is constrained
by a kind of necessity (2.12.2); but his will is also free, because he makes only some
of the things which it is in his power to make (2.12.9), so he is clearly exercising
choice in this. He doesn't work haphazardly but follows a plan, and Ficino inveighs
heavily against Lucretius for suggesting otherwise (2.13.6–7); the wonderful
complexity of nature makes it clear “that all things are made and ruled by
the providence of the one all-knowing craftsman” (2.13.7 — I guess this is
an example of the (in)famous ‘watchmaker analogy’).
If god created the world, why is it so full of imperfections? Ficino handwaves
this a little, saying that “the absolutely highest perfection should not be sought
for in the whole work” (2.13.9), and especially not in any individual part — it's
enough that each part is in harmony with the rest: “we will find that the world
cannot be better arranged than it is”. I don't see any sort of convincing argument
here, and I suspect he's really going in the opposite direction: he is already convinced
that god is perfect, so he can't accept the idea that god created an imperfect universe,
so he can't help concluding that if you look at the universe carefully, you will find that
it cannot be better arranged than it is.
If god created the world and moves everything in it, how can people have any sort
of free will? Ficino handwaves this as well, assuring us that we totally do have
free will, but it just so happens that god knows in advance what exactly it is that we'll
freely choose to do (2.13.10) :S
Book III
This book starts with a sort of summary overview of the five levels or essences
that we encountered in Book I. Ficino compares them in various ways, but a bit
more systematically than before: God is motionless unity; angel is motionless plurality,
it moves others (i.e. acts on them; 3.1.12);
soul is plurality subject to movement, but also partly immobile (3.1.9);
quality is completely mobile, subject to change even in its essence, but at least
it can also change/move other things (namely bodies); but body is only subject to
movement but does not move other things (3.1.10).
He emphasizes the importance of the soul as the intermediate level in this scheme,
“nature's center, the mean of everything in the universe” (3.2.6).
The gap between the immutable god and angels on the one hand,
and the completely inactive body on the other hand, is too big and requires an intermediate
level that can be in contact with both of these (3.1.13), i.e. the soul. God and
angel are eternal and incorporeal (undivided in time and dimension),
body and quality are purely temporal and corporeal (dispersed in time and dimension);
angel is immobile, quality is constantly changing, all of which again requires an
intermediate level between them (3.2.1, 3.2.5).
The soul connects these extremes; it is in contact with the body everywhere,
but not divided the way quality is — the whole soul is present in the body everywhere
(3.2.3–4), so in a certain sense it is both divided and undivided (3.2.5).
It is in contact with the higher levels through understanding them (3.2.9).
The lower two levels, body and quality, are moved by others, but the soul is moved
by itself (3.1.12). The soul is where the first movement is located (as the upper
two levels are immobile); in fact this motion coming from an internal power is what
we describe as life: the soul gives life to the body (3.2.7).
Book IV
If there's one thing you can rely upon the Neoplatonists to do, it's to
obsessively divide everything into levels and sublevels. ‘When in
doubt, just insert another level’ could well be their most important motto.
In this book we see a little of what you might call cosmology or astronomy,
though Ficino does not enter into a really systematic exposition of it.
From what I gather here, the world consists of four “spheres” associated
with the elements (from heavier to lighter, and thus from lower to higher:
earth, water, air, fire), and above it there are eight heavenly “spheres”
associated with the various astronomical bodies (probably Moon, Sun, Mercury, Venus,
Mars, Jupiter, Saturn, and the fixed stars).
But what really interests Ficino here is to demonstrate that each
of these twelve spheres has a soul. As we already saw earlier, for him the soul
is something that gives life and motion to a body. Earth and water generate and
“nourish” various living beings, cause plants to grow from seeds and
so on (4.1.2; and sometimes living things are even “born by putrefaction”, without
any seeds at all — 4.1.6), therefore clearly* the spheres of earth and water have
a soul from which this life-giving power comes. And if these lower spheres have
souls, then surely the higher and “much purer” spheres of air and fire
must have souls too (4.1.12).
[*Or maybe not so clearly: Ficino takes care to argue why this power
comes from soul and not e.g. from God (4.1.9) or angel (4.1.10). For example,
these higher principles are too indivisible and incorporeal to be compatible
with the task of giving form to matter, but the soul is just right for that (4.1.10).]
For the heavenly spheres, the argument that they are alive (and thus
have a soul) seems to be mostly based on their regular motion (4.1.17, 21).
This motion cannot come from quality, which is too limited and would get exhausted (4.1.17),
nor directly from God, who cannot be divided between the spheres (but each sphere
moves differently on its own, 4.1.18–19), nor from angel (which, as we know, is completely
immobile; 4.1.20–1). Thus the motion of the spheres can only come from the soul.
That individual animals have individual souls also follows from the fact that they
can move independently of the sphere of earth or water that they otherwise inhabit (4.1.22).
Ficino even provides the “names of the divine souls”, two for each sphere,
from one of the ancient Greek hymns attributed to Orpheus (4.1.28).
Besides the souls of the spheres, there are of course also the individual
souls of the various individual creatures living in those spheres; we are familiar
with animals living in earth and water, but apparently there also exist
“airy and fiery creatures” (4.1.13), which are unfortunately invisible
to us. Individual stars, those “celestial animals” (4.1.13), have souls too.
In the lower spheres (earth and water), some of these individual souls are rational, some irrational
(in the higher ones, all are rational); e.g. in the sphere of water, the souls of fish are irrational,
those of “water daemons” or “Nereids” are rational (4.1.14) :))
“Their bodies are sometimes seen by sharper eyes, especially in Persia and Africa”,
and Porphyry reports that some daemons can even be touched (ibid.).
Ficino also mentions a delightfully wacky Pythagorean belief that in
each sphere, between the soul of the sphere and the souls of individual creatures
there is a layer of “twelve principal souls” (4.1.15), which then
rule over the numberless individual souls below them (4.1.16). In the sphere
of stars the twelve principal souls are tied to the twelve signs of the zodiac;
in the sphere of earth, the twelve principal souls correspond to twelve types of
human personality (which arise from different proportions of reason, irascibility,
and desire).
Above the souls of the twelve spheres there is one “soul of the world” (4.1.23).
This soul connects the spheres, gives them a cetain unity, and enables them to be
in “sympathy” with each other (ibid.). This seems to be another one
of those unstated Neoplatonic axioms, and I remember also seeing it at work in Plotinus and in Ficino's
commentaries upon him: that for two things to be connected, or to have any sort of influence upon each
other, it is necessary that there exist some sort of soul which is simultaneously present,
in its entirety, in both of them, and it is through this soul that a connection between those
two things is possible.
Towards the end of this book, Ficino writes a bit more about the motion
of the souls of spheres. He says this is circular motion because it is the most
perfect kind of motion, as it is the most similar to being at rest (4.1.10; I guess the idea
is that if a circle rotates around its own centre, it will actually look like the
same circle all the time). But why do the spheres rotate at all? Well, apparently
“the matter of the world cannot possess all the figures in heaven
at the same time” and it therefore rotates “so that it can attain by
succession [. . .] what it cannot attain at rest” (4.1.8).
And it seems there is also a mechanism whereby the movement of each sphere causes
the next inner sphere to move as well, because each particle of the inner sphere
“yearns to come into contact with all the particles” of the outer
sphere (4.1.10). But I don't see why both spheres would have to rotate for
this; if the outer sphere rotates, the inner sphere could stand at rest and
it would still eventually come into contact with all points of the outer sphere...
*
Marsilio Ficino: Platonic Theology. Vol. 2: Books V–VIII.
English translation by Michael J. B. Allen with John Warden.
Latin text edited by James Hankins with William Bowen.
The I Tatti Renaissance Library, Vol. 4.
Harvard University Press, 2002.
0674007646.
v + 397 pp.
Book V
In this book, Ficino presents something like fifteen arguments that the (rational)
soul is immortal. This stuff was mostly very abstract and hard for me to understand,
and the various arguments don't seem to have all that much in common with each other,
but I couldn't help being impressed that he managed to approach the subject from so
many different directions. The other books in the present volume are organized along
similar lines, by the way. In mathematics, it is enough to have one proof of a theorem :],
but perhaps in philosophy one feels safer to have a dozen or more.
• For example: we saw earlier that soul is the level at which movement begins
(the higher levels,
angel and God, are motionless), and so this movement must be perpetual, otherwise
“nothing else in nature would be moved”; and since this “internal
movement is life”, it follows that soul is immortal (5.1.2).
• But we also saw that the soul is partly motionless — its substance
doesn't change; and therefore it also can't stop existing, so it is immortal (5.2.2).
• Soul endows matter with form, and since matter can't stop existing, it follows
that the soul can't either, so it is immortal (5.4.10). Why can't matter be destroyed?
It cannot be dissolved into parts because it doesn't really have parts (those come with
quantity), and it cannot be destroyed by contact with an opposite quality since no
quality is opposite to it — matter can receive any quality (5.4.7).
Once again I find his notion of matter easier to understand if I think of it as space...
• A similar but more direct argument: soul itself cannot be broken into parts
since it is not divided in the body; nor can it be destroyed by receiving an opposite
quality, “for the first subject exposed to passion is matter” (5.5.6).
Soul inclines towards matter, but does not depend on it (5.5.4–5).
• There's a nice explanation of the difference between essence and existence (5.7.1):
the former is more like a definition, the “rational principle of a thing”;
for example, a comet is such-and-such a thing, and this is true even if no comets happen
to exist at the moment. But existence is “the act of its essence”, the
presence of the thing at a specific place and time.
Ficino then asserts that soul (or any other form), when it is separated from matter,
exists in itself, i.e. it receives its existence from its essence, and essence is
immortal, so that soul is also immortal (5.7.4). This strikes me as cheating — a kind
of argument by definition. In this view, soul exists in the same sense that e.g. Pythagorean
triples exist; but that's hardly what people have in mind when they dream about immortality.
Elsewhere he similarly asserts that soul “exists entirely in itself separate
from body” (5.9.4), and since “nothing departs from itself” it will
always inhere in itself and therefore alwasy exist. Another similar argument is that
soul, “being related to unchangeable God through its own unchangeable essence,
it remains unchanging” (5.10.5) and thus is immortal.
Still elsewhere he says that if the soul is destroyed, “it loses its existence,
yet its essence survives” (5.11.3), so the soul is immortal in that sense.
• A thing ceases to exist when it is separated from its form (5.8.1);
for instance, the same matter is still there, but no longer arranged in the form of a dog,
so it's no longer a dog. The matter could exist without being arranged in that particular
form, so the object (composed of matter and form) can cease to exist (5.12.2).
But soul is a simple form, not a composite of e.g. matter and some other form (5.12.4);
soul is a “simple form, subsisting in itself” (5.12.1), or in other words,
soul cannot be separated from its form, its “essence is the
form of itself” (5.8.5). Thus soul cannot cease to exist.
• As we already saw earlier, soul is what gives life to living beings;
“life is the property of soul” and God “never takes from anything
what is its own property” (5.12.7), so soul is immortal. Argument by strong
faith :P
Or in other words, “soul from its very essence is life” (5.14.2),
and a form cannot receive its opposite (5.14.2), so soul cannot receive death (as the
opposite of life) and is hence immortal. Ficino later clarifies that this all applies
to the rational soul, whereas the irrational soul “is not a true soul”,
it just animates the body and doesn't exist in itself (5.14.7). He then lists the
opinions of various philosophers as to whether the irrational soul is immortal or not.
• God is the ultimate source of all existence: “That you exist, you have
from God alone. That you are human, you owe to a human being too; that you are warm,
to a fire.” (5.13.3.) To really create something, from nothing, requires infinite
power, and God alone can do that (5.13.9); thus the essence of soul is “made directly
by God” and he preserves things by the same power with which he created them,
so soul is immortal (5.13.12).
• The soul governs the body, not vice versa; it can change or move the body,
but the body can't change the soul, e.g. when the body dies (5.15.3). The soul can
remember the past or imagine the future, so it is in a way above time; when the
body moves (or changes), the soul doesn't really change because both the old and the
new state were in a way already in it (5.15.3).
Book VI
Ficino starts with an account of a discussion that he apparently had with a number
of prominent Florentine intellectuals, in which some of them suggested that his arguments
so far had indeed shown that the third essence (or level of being) was immortal, but
not yet that the rational soul was in fact on that third level. Various ideas are then
put forth as to how the soul might actually be corporeal: perhaps it's a “very fine
miniature body spread throughout our grosser body” (6.1.3), or a kind of quality
either spread through the body (6.1.4) or a point attached to some part of the body
like the heart or brain (6.1.5), or present throughout the body but somehow arising
out of it (6.1.6). For each of these views he lists various ancient philosophers
that supported it. This was impressive to see, but also confirmed my impressions that
philosophers don't actually know anything about anything, they just argue endlessly (and pointlessly).
Ficino intends to refute these views, since to him it was of course very
important that the soul be incorporeal. He says that the ideas about soul being
corporeal largely arise from a simple mistake: people are used to perceiving the
world around them with their senses, which detect only corporeal things, so they
think that the soul must be corporeal too; to get a truer understanding of the
soul, you should use your mind instead (6.2.3–4), which will allow you to appreciate
what the pure soul is like (i.e. apart from being trapped in the body; 6.2.10).
Our senses often deceive us, after all, or give us an incomplete picture 6.2.7–8).
He mentions two famous thought experiments connected with this. Avicenna imagined
a man born without any senses; such a man would not be used to perceiving any body-like characteristics such as “color, length, or breadth”, so he would certainly not imagine
his soul as having them either — he would imagine it as incorporeal (6.2.11–12).
This confirms that those who imagine the soul to be corporeal are simply misled by their senses.
— The other thought experiment is Plato's story about prisoners in a cave, who
could see only shadows of things on a wall, rather than the things themselves.
To Ficino our visible, sensible world is also such a shadow, and we should strive to use our
minds to study the truer, higher, divine invisible world (6.2.14–15).
He has a couple of arguments as to why non-material things exist. If you start with
a body and gradually abstract away its three dimensions and even its location, you end up
with a sort of point-like unity completely separated from space;
the more abstract something is, the more perfect it is;* so, since body existed, that final
incorporeal unity must also exist, since it is more pefect than the body (6.2.16).
[*This seems to be another of those Neoplatonic axioms, this time even stated explicitly: “rational thought, when it is ascending, is not deceived” (6.2.16).]
Besides, things like light are incorporeal, and everybody agrees that light exists (6.2.18).
He then asserts that the visible light of the stars and planets “depends on”
the invisible spiritual light in the souls of those objects (6.2.19–20).
• One of the functions of the soul is nourishment (vegetative soul), which causes
bodies to grow; if the soul were corporeal, all bodies would have that power; but some
don't (e.g. stones), so soul must be incorporeal (6.4.1).
• Each body is either soulless or ensouled. If soul were a soulless body, that is
clearly absurd; if it were an ensouled body, there would have to exist some other soul by
which it is ensouled, and then you'd have the same problem about this other soul. The only
option then is that soul is not a body at all, i.e. it's incorporeal (6.5.1). (I wonder
why the soul couldn't be ensouled by itself?)
• If soul were corporeal, it would be based on one of the elements, maybe fire;
but then all things on fire would be alive, which they clearly aren't (6.6.1).
Also, if something is corporeal, our senses could perceive it; but they can't perceive
the soul, so it must be incorporeal (6.6.3).
• Body, Ficino says, is composed of matter and form (interesting; in book 1 he said
matter and quantity). If soul were also a body, it would likewise be composed of these
two things, and it would then need some other principle that would compose them into a
whole; and then that other principle would really be what we should call soul (6.7.1).
• Body is dispersed in space and “subject to opposing qualities” (e.g.
heat and cold; 6.8.1); something incorporeal is needed to make it into a whole, and that's
the soul: it is “not body, but the body's inner bond or binding substance” (6.8.3).
• The soul, as something that gives the body its unity, is simultaneously present
in its entirety everywhere in the body, and this is something that is clearly impossible
for a corporeal thing; thus soul is incorporeal (6.9–10).
• Soul is the source of motion, but a body isn't self-moving; thus the soul must
be incorporeal. The claim that the body can't move itself seems to rely mostly on the
fact that it's divisible, so you could have some parts of the body moving either themselves
or other parts, but in no case can you say that the body as a whole moves itself as a whole (6.12.2).
The soul, being indivisible, does not have this problem.
Ficino goes on to list all the specific kinds of motion and then argues, for each of them,
why the body is incapable of it (but the soul is). For me this was mostly interesting because
it finally illustrates what he means by motion: “All the motions are these: alteration,
generation, corruption, growth, diminution, condensation, rarefaction, and progression”
(6.12.9). So it's true, as we said earlier, that to him ‘motion’ is more like
what we would call ‘change’.
• If the soul were corporeal, then e.g. larger bodies would have a larger soul with
greater powers: “In a huge body the rational soul will be more noble and more divine.”
(6.13.2) This could be the premiss of a nice science-fiction story, with blue whales being
the noblest beings, lording it over elephants, with humans somewhere far below :)
Book VII
This book provides yet more arguments that the soul must be incorporeal, this time
with a focus on its capacity for sense-perception. Basically, Ficino argues in various ways
that senses couldn't work if the soul were corporeal. Nowadays we know a bit more about
how our senses work, with the cells in our eyes, our brains and so on, so we do not think
it odd that it all arises from these purely material phenomena. To us today, our perceptions,
our thoughts, our very life are just abstractions arising out of the complex interplay of
biological processes in our cells, electrical impulses firing in our brains and so on.
But Ficino couldn't imagine that things could work that way, and wouldn't accept such
a material explanation of them.
Instead, he has some very odd and literal ideas about how bodily senses would have to
work, and naturally he concludes them to be absurd. “Whenever body receives something,
it receives in a corporeal manner” (7.1.2) — meaning that e.g. if it was our
body that saw something, this means that the image of that thing would have to be somehow
imprinted on our body like a seal is imprinted on wax. This means we couldn't see something
larger than ourselves, nor could we imagine two things at once (just like you can't imprint
two different seals on the same piece of wax simultaneously).
• Furthermore, we have five senses, but clearly we also have some sort of power that
integrates their perceptions together; to accomplish this, that power must be indivisible (7.2.3);
so it cannot be corporeal (but is part of our incorporeal soul). Here we again see one of
those unstated Neoplatonic axioms at work: for two separate things to somehow be
connected or work together, there must exist some mysterious linking thing (like the soul here)
that is present in its entirety in both of them at once and thereby connects them.
Neoplatonists just can't stand the idea of anything functioning at a distance.
• If senses were present in the body, they would be “distended by corporeal
bulk” (7.4.1), so each sense-perception would be infinitely divided, just like body is;
so we wouldn't be able e.g. to see any object as a whole — clearly absurd.
• Ficino also has some interesting arguments based on our internal senses of what
is happening inside our body. For instance, if something injures your foot, your whole
attention is turned that way — it isn't just the foot that feels this and reacts to it.
This can only work because our soul unites all parts of the body and the perceptions coming
from them (7.5.1). Otherwise each part of the body would feel its own pain only and would
be unaware of what is happening elsewhere (7.5.4).
• He introduces an interesting new concept: “the soul, since it is most
pure, is linked to this gross and earthy body, which is so different from it, only by means
of a superlatively fine, transparent, diminutive body which we call the spirit.
It is generated by the heart's heat our of the finest part of the blood and thence spread
through the whole body.” (7.6.1) Our hypothetical foot injury damages the foot and
the corresponding part of the spirit, but not the soul, otherwise the soul wouldn't feel
anything (since the relevant part would already be damaged or missing; 7.6.1–2).
(Later he describes the spirit as “that warm living vapor [. . .] the knot of the soul and body”; 9.5.2.)
• Ficino also argues that the soul is not merely the “complexion” of
the body, this being “a technical medical term meaning a commixture or tempering,
especially of humors in the animate body” (note 13 on p. 383). This complexion,
he says, is merely an “accidental form” which arises from the body with its
various contrary qualities (7.9.1); but the soul is a “substantial form”, a
substance: it defines the species to which the body will belong (e.g. man or dog),
and only after that will the complexion be able to appear at all; and “when the soul
leaves, the body fades away” and so does complexion (7.9.2).
• He similarly denies that the soul could be merely “a kind of harmony
born from the complexion” (7.10), because then it would again be just accidental;
besides, every body has some kind of harmony, but not every body is alive, which it would
be if it had a soul (7.11); and there is a kind of harmony within each part of the body
too, but it would be absurd to say that each part has its own soul (7.12). Besides,
compare an upright man and a thief: the former is “more in tune” and thus has
more harmony; so if soul were harmony, he'd have a stronger soul and would thus be more
lively than the thief (since soul gives life), but we know that this isn't necessarily
the case (7.14).
Book VIII
What the previous book did for sense-perception, this one does for understanding,
i.e. it argues that the soul couldn't perform this function if it weren't incorporeal
(and hence immortal).
Ficino starts by introducing an interesting hierarchy of increasingly abstract
abilities: sensation, imagination, phantasy [sic], and understanding (8.1.2). With sensation
you e.g. see a specific person when he is in front of you; with imagination you can
also recall that image to memory when the person isn't there; with phantasy you can
make judgments about the image, e.g. recognise who that person is and what he is like (8.1.3);
with the understanding (or intellect) you can perform abstractions, e.g. by comparing
different people or identifying common features of humans as a whole (8.1.4).
• Some of the arguments for the incorporeal nature of the soul in this book are a bit
odd. The soul, he says, feeds on truth, just like the body feeds on food; your body
stops being hungry when you've had enough food, but your soul never stops being hungry
for more truth, so the soul is incorporeal (8.2.7). Truth itself is, of course, also
incorporeal, otherwise “it would not be present in incorporeal entities”
like God and angels (8.2.9).
• Some arguments are similar as in the previous book: if the soul were corporeal,
then a larger person with a larger body would also have a larger soul and thus
stronger mental powers, he'd be wiser and more just, etc., which is obviously not
true in general (8.3.4).
• For (abstract) thinking to work, the soul has to receive immaterial things which
are variously called “universal forms” or “concepts” or
“rational principles” (8.4.1), and such indivisible immaterial things
cannot be received by the body or by quality (form divided in body), which are divisible
(“indivisibles are only grasped by indivisibles”, 8.5.3);
so the soul has to be incorporeal. Also, a material body couldn't receive
universal forms because it is tied to a particular place and time (8.8.1).
• The intellect has to be indivisible because, when you understand something,
you do it with your whole intellect, you can't just understand it with a part of your
intellect (8.6.1).
• A body loses its form when it receives a new one (e.g. if a cold object
becomes hot), but the intellect can receive any form (think about any concept)
without losing its form (it still remains intellect), so clearly it can't be some kind of body
(8.7.1). He returns to this argument several times, rephrasing it in terms of motion
(8.11; remember that for him, “motion” really means “change”),
and emphasizing that the mind does not change when it receives forms (just like a mirror
doesn't change when it reflects an image; 8.13.1). And since it does not change,
“it receives nothing from outside which would change or destroy it”, so
it is immortal (8.13.4).
• Two bodies cannot be one inside the other and vice versa at the same time;
but two minds can understand one another like that, so clearly minds are incorporeal (8.9.1).
• Bodies don't act outside their species (“a dog for instance never
gives birth to a sheep”, 8.10.1), but a mind can easily receive the forms of many kinds
of bodies and even incorporeal concepts; so it must be incorporeal itself (8.10.3).
• A mind can entertain two contrary concepts at the same time, but
a body can't e.g. be hot and cold at the same time (8.12); so the mind must be incorporeal.
• The mind must be non-material because it can rise above material things,
e.g. by imagining something that isn't there, abstracting specific objects into their
species, etc. (8.14.1).
• Mind “is moved of its own free will, it gazes at itself [. . .]
and it acts for its own benefit” (8.15.1). That is, the mind's activity begins
and ends in itself, and runs entirely inside itself; so the mind lives and exists
through itself, and is therefore immortal (8.15.6). (By contrast, the activity of the
body is directed at some external end.)
• The mind has a certain grasp of infinity, by things which we might describe
as induction, abstraction and so on; it can discover “infinite act, which is God”,
and “infinite potency”, i.e. “matter [. . .] capable of receiving
from Him numberless forms” (8.16.5). Something corporeal couldn't have such
infinite powers, so the mind must be incorporeal.
*
Marsilio Ficino: Platonic Theology. Vol. 3: Books IX–XI.
English translation by Michael J. B. Allen with John Warden.
Latin text edited by James Hankins with William Bowen.
The I Tatti Renaissance Library, Vol. 7.
Harvard University Press, 2003.
0674010655.
v + 362 pp.
Book IX
This book is dedicated to (yet more) arguments that the soul is independent
of the body, which, together with the already often demonstrated fact that
it is indivisible, should be enough to prove its immortality (9.1.1).
• Ficino points out that the mind can reflect upon itself; e.g., when
you understand something, you understand that you are understanding (9.1.3).
But a bodily thing could not reflect upon itself, because a body is
divided into parts and you could have parts reflecting upon parts or upon the
whole, but not really the whole upon the whole (9.1.2). But this struck
me as little more but another way of saying that the soul must be indivisible.
• He also gives examples of people making prophecies in their
sleep or shortly before dying (9.2.2), and says that this demonstrates that the soul
works the better the more it is separated from the body — a sign of the
soul's independence of the body.
• The soul often actively resists the body, e.g. when in contemplation it
ascends towards non-corporeal concepts (9.3.2) or when it resists, at least
temporarily, some bodily urges (9.3.6). This shows that the soul does not
originate in the body, otherwise it wouldn't be able to resist it.
• The behaviour of other animals is compelled by their nature or
instinct, but humans can choose to behave differently (9.4.3, 5), which shows
that our rational soul can act free of the body, unlike the irrational souls of other
animals. Different people can behave differently and have different opinions,
unlike animals, where all members of a species behave the same (9.4.14).
Our soul is so free that even the astrological influence of stars upon us
is only limited (9.4.14).
• The soul gives form to the body and controls it,
rather than vice versa (9.5.2). When our mind performs abstract thinking,
“any corporeal instrument interposed between us” and the
abstract concepts “would be a hindrance” (9.5.13), so that
part of our soul at least does not depend on the body, but acts without it.
And since the soul does not exist through the body, it won't die with it
either (9.5.30).
• Man has a dual nature: such things as nutrition and sensation,
the corporeal nature of our body, are like those found in the other animals,
and are likewise mortal; but our “power of contemplating will be immortal,
being concerned with immortal things and shared in common with the
immortals” (9.6.4; i.e. with God, angels, souls of the heavenly
spheres etc.).
• Animals have a mortal (irrational) soul in a mortal
body; the heavenly spheres have an immortal soul in an incorruptible
body; but we have an intermediate position, an immortal soul in a
perishable body (9.7.3–4).
Book X
In another example of the Neoplatonic obsession with hierarchies,
Ficino introduces the order of bodies (10.1.2), from highest (“heaven on
high”, by which I guess he means the eight heavenly spheres, or
perhaps just the highest of them?) to lowest (prime matter). Above this order
there is also the order of intellects
(or minds; 10.1.3), from highest (God) to lowest (the human mind; 10.1.6).
In each order, the higher things are more active and govern the ones below, which
are more passive (they receive forms). (But perhaps this division into two
orders is just another way of describing the familiar distinction between the
sensible universe and the intelligible universe?) Anyway, Ficino argues
that even the lowest body (matter) is incorruptible and can only be created by God,
so therefore the lowest intellect (human mind) — which is in a higher order than
the lowest body — can also only come from God and be incorruptible (and thus
immortal; 10.1.4).
Next comes another fascinating hierarchy, which he calls the chain of being (10.2.2–3),
consisting of several orders where the lowest part of one order is quite close to the
highest part of the next lower order. First there is the aether, by which
he seems to mean the eight celestial spheres; next there are the elements, i.e. the
four elemental spheres (and he tells us that the lowest of the heavenly spheres, i.e.
the moon, and the highest of the elements, i.e. fire, are close to each other). Below
the elements are the composites: dense vapours and smokes (still close to elements),
porous rocks, solid rocks, metals like iron and lead, and finally silver and gold (close to plants).
Next is the order of plants, from tubers (close to metals) to trees (close to animals);
next is the order of animals, from oysters (close to trees) to “beasts that
resemble men” (mammals); and finally the order of men, from “dullwitted,
lazy men” (close to animals) to “heroic men” (close to “the divine spirits”).
Next is the order of spirits, from lower ones (daemons or heroes) to higher ones (angels;
he gives a rudimentary version of the angelic hierarchy). Wow! This reminded me a lot
of the stark raving lunacy of Plato's Timaeus,
but Ficino goes a few steps farther :)
His reason for introducing this hierarchy is to explain how something of divine
origin, like our soul, can be stuck in matter the way it is. Just like in the chain
of being the lowest end of one order touches the highest end of the next lower order,
so our soul lies at the point where the “lowest intellect is linked with the highest
of the sensitive souls” (10.2.4). Our soul has an intermediate position between
immortal spirits outside the body (angels) above us, and mortal spirits inside the body
(irrational souls of animals) below us; our soul is therefore inside the body, but immortal (10.2.6).
It governs the body below it and contemplates the divine things above it (10.3.7).
It is the highest form in the order of bodies and is only partly attached to the body (the
intellect is not attached; 10.3.8).
He even cites some really kooky ancient Neoplatonic ideas which suggest that this applies
not only to men but also to some daemons, who may be “happier and far longer-lived
than men” but nevertheless mortal (10.2.7); and he mentions Plutarch's famous story about
the death
of Pan as an example of such a daemon's mortality (10.2.8).
The descent of the soul into the body is a gradual process: first it gets a “celestial
body of air”, then “a spirit generated from the heart”, and only then does
it really enter into the body (10.2.13).
God, when creating our body, first forms prime matter into elements, these into
humours, these into limbs, and then adds the forms of nutrition, feeling and understanding (10.3.2).
I found this interesting as it illustrates just how broad a sense the word “form”
as for him — it seems to be far more than just a simple mental abstraction that
you hear about in Plato (the form of a dog etc.).
Ficino later goes into more details about the technicalities of creation. God first
“conditions” the prime matter with “prime qualities”,
which come in four pairs: rarity/density, lightness/heaviness, heat/cold, wetness/and dryness (10.5.1).
Based on different mixtures of these, matter can then receive the species or forms
of elements; e.g. fire is based on rarity, lightness, heat and dryness. Blending
the four elements results in the forms of composite materials like stones and metals (10.5.2).
Next come the forms of plants, which include such capabilities as life, procreation,
and some movement (10.5.3); then the souls (forms) of animals, which add the abilities
of sense and knowledge (10.5.4); and finally the human soul, which also has the power
of understanding, and in this it resembles “the minds of heaven” (10.5.5).
Our soul must be non-material since matter impedes such abilities as sight, knowing and
understanding (10.5.6).
• There's an interesting section about the creation of forms in matter
(the point, again, will be to explain how our soul can be stuck in matter). In our body,
the soul causes food to be digested (usign heat as its instrument) and turned into various forms: lower (bones),
intermediate (flesh and sinews), and highest (the spirit); 10.4.2. Similarly, an artist or craftman
uses his instruments (tools) to create various forms in matter, from lower (e.g. furniture)
to intermediate (paintings, buildings) to highest (discourses, songs, music); 10.4.3.
Ficino argues that God will similarly create various forms in matter, from lowest
to highest; and the highest, the one most like him, will surely have to be immortal, otherwise
it would not be “a perfect and complete image”. This highest form is our soul,
which is therefore immortal (10.4.4).
Our soul may be the highest of the bodily forms (10.5.8), but our mind is the
lowest of the intellects: the ensouled (animated) mind (10.6.2). While it is ensouled,
even its contemplation of the divine relies on being stimulated by images arising out of
our senses and phantasy, and these two faculties “operate through the corporeal spirits”
(10.6.2). But later it leaves images behind as it ascends towards more abstract concepts (10.6.6).
• More on how the immaterial soul can be produced in matter: Ficino tries
to explain this by analogies, like how the sun produces “light in the air but
not from the air”, or how the reflection is “in the mirror but not from the mirror”
(10.7.1). Similarly God creates the rational soul in matter, and since he is eternal,
it is eternal as well (10.7.6).
• Ficino asserts that “Everything comes to rest in its proper end.
Its proper end is its proper cause.” (10.8.2) He tries to demonstrate that
for our souls, this end (and hence cause) is nothing other than God himself.
Our mind is inclined to inquire about the causes of things, going farther and
farther back up the chain of causes until it reaches God (= truth).
Similarly, our will keeps desiring the good and is not content with anything less
than the infinite good, i.e. with God (10.8.4).
“No effect extends beyond its cause”
(10.8.8), so given that our soul doesn't stop until it has ascended all the way to
God in its yearning for truth and goodness, it clearly can't have been created
by anything lesser than God.
• He also asserts that the object of some activity always conforms to
that activity and to the power which gives rise to that activity. For example,
sight (activity) uses its “inner ray” (power) to detect the things
we see (object; 10.9.1). (This refers to the old theory of how sight works, namely that
our eyes emit some kind of ray, which touches another ray coming from the object
of our sight, and it is this contact between the rays that allows us to see the
object. But Ficino has examples for other senses as well, which are less misguided.)
Regardless of what we think of his example involving sight, what he really wants
to use this principle for is the mind, of course. Its objects (what it tries to
contemplate, namely rational principles) are non-material and eternal, so clearly
mind itself must also be non-material and eternal (10.9.2).
Book XI
Ficino argues that our mind or intellect is immortal because, in its
business of understanding things, it is bound up very closely with such eternal and
immaterial things as “rational principles” and “species” (11.5.10).
From my point of view all this was quite strange and mostly showed what a very
unusual view he had of how minds and understanding work. He insists that,
when the intellect understands something, it is joined and merged with the
thing understood (the intelligible); 11.1.2.
And such intelligible things
as definitions of things and properties of species are eternal: a man is
always a rational animal, even if no man happens to be alive at the moment (11.1.3).
And such an eternal universal species therefore cannot arise out of the
actual mortal men that may or may not be alive at any given moment; instead,
such abstractions arise out of the intellect (11.2.2) — the intellect, in
understanding a thing, really understands something that arose out of itself (11.2.4).
It's masturbation navel-gazing all the way down!
Later he tries to go into a little more detail about how this is supposed
to work. He insists that “species” or “universals”
are produced by the mind out of itself (11.3.8), not out of images delivered by our imagination
or phantasms delivered by our phantasy. For example, your mind couldn't get its concept
of human nature from your observations of actual concrete people, because in them
human nature is mixed with accidental properties (e.g. the details of each individual's
appearance; 11.3.4) and, besides, you can't possibly have seen all people (11.3.5).
So I guess what he's trying to say that the key part of developing a universal
concept must occur in the mind (by abstracting from what you have seen and unifying
the various images into one concept), and so in that sense this concept came
from the mind and not from outside images (these images can only trigger the process, 11.3.8).
Similarly, he points out that you won't find perfect unity, goodness, beauty, etc. in
bodies, so our ideas of these things can't come from images and sensations (11.4.18);
our mind must have got these Ideas from above and they are then innate in it (11.4.22).
There are also a couple of what you might call arguments from incredulity.
For example: our soul actually descends from God with all the Ideas already
embedded in it — because surely he would not have made it less perfect
than that (11.3.9) :)) Or: we see that the lowest part of the soul,
which is in charge of nourishing the body, contains from the start the principles
of such things as body parts, so that it is able to form those body parts;
so then surely the highest part of the soul, namely the mind, will also be filled
with rational principles from the start (11.3.10).
Animals can't form abstractions but people can; abstractions must therefore
come from what people have that animals lack, i.e. from the intellect (11.3.13).
Certain concepts and principles of reasoning are self-evident to us, which shows
that they must be innate in our minds (11.3.15, 18). For example, all people
have an innate ability to judge what is beautiful, what is true, etc. (11.5.1, 11.6.15).
Even teaching, in Ficino's view, isn't so much about transferring information
from the teacher to the student, but rather about the teacher helping the student
discover things which are in some sense already innate in his mind (11.5.7).
This innateness also explains why people are sometimes able to discover things
by themselves (11.5.8).
In fact the “species” he spoke about earlier in this book seem
to be more or less the same thing as Plato's “Ideas” (11.4.2).
These Ideas (or “rational principles” or “universal forms of
things”) “move and form and perfect the intellect” (11.4.4),
so they are higher than it. They are present as one single form in God/unity
(the first hypostasis of Plotinus & co.) and as multiple forms in
“the intelligible” (second hypostasis; 11.4.6).
Rational principles of things must be present in their causes (11.4.12),
so it makes sense that the Ideas of everything must be in God as the ultimate cause.
Other lower causes are just the “instruments of the first cause” (11.4.14).
P.S. Some people talk about the birds and the bees. . . some about the sun:
“In human generation for instance, because the
sun generates man through the medium of a man, the begetting man has more in
common with the begotten man than the sun has.” (11.3.5) :))
*
Marsilio Ficino: Platonic Theology. Vol. 4: Books XII–XIV.
English translation by Michael J. B. Allen.
Latin text edited by James Hankins with William Bowen.
The I Tatti Renaissance Library, Vol. 13.
Harvard University Press, 2004.
0674014820.
vii + 371 pp.
Book XII
The purpose of this book is to argue that the soul is immortal because our
mind is constantly being formed by God and filled by him with understanding.
Ficino starts by describing Plato's theory about how our mind ascends
from “the perception of bodily forms” (e.g. seeing a circle-shaped
object) to abstract Ideas (e.g. the idea of a circle), which are divine and
external to us. The intermediate step here involves “formulae of the ideas”,
which are innate in our mind (12.1.1); e.g. “the mind through the formula
of man adapts itself to the idea of man” (12.2.2). (I just now realized that
“formula” probably originated as a Latin diminutive of the word
“form”, and the latter is sometimes used as a synonym of “idea”.)
The way understanding works is that our mind is “being formed by
the divine understanding” (12.1.2), i.e. we receive forms from God,
in whom truth resides (or rather he himself is the truth). Our mind thereby
becomes “joined to God” (12.2.3) — a very mystical view of
things, which reminded me a little of the proverbial new-ager at the hot-dog
stand: ‘make me one with everything’
:) Understanding
consists of the mind “matching itself to the idea” (12.3.1).
Ideas or “rational principles” of things are unchanging and precede
the creation of those things, so they can't be anywhere else than in God (12.1.7).
Ficino points out that many ancient philosophers “combined the study
of philosophy with religious piety” (12.1.14).
Then Ficino makes something of a detour explaining the Neoplatonic view that
unity, and not being, is the highest principle (12.3.6; and thus equivalent to God),
and why it is furthermore the same as goodness (12.3.7; because “all things
seek the good absolutely but not being absolutely, just well-being”. But
didn't we already see things along these lines in Book I?
He has a very charming metaphor: “God creates souls, then places
Himself in front of them, as though they were mirrors: in this way reflections
of God are formed in individuals. These reflections are souls' minds”
(12.4.2). Our mind is the link between our soul and God (12.4.5). It continually
receives divine forms much like prime matter receives natural forms,
and is thus immortal similarly to how prime matter is incorruptible (12.4.8, 10).
The remainder of the book gives various examples that illustrate
how our mind constantly receives its understanding from God:
• In judging the visual images brought to it by the senses (e.g. in art or architecture),
our mind relies on notions of unity, beauty, symmetry, etc., which are
innate and unchanging and cannot come from any other than God (12.5.7).
• When two people, during the course of an argument, agree that something is
true, it is not a matter of one of them seeing this truth in the other, but rather
both of them “see it in that unchangeable truth which is above our minds”
(12.5.15).
• When we listen to music or a song, our ability to judge the harmony and rhythm
does not come from the sounds we hear, but is inside our mind (e.g. because it
“does not cease to exist when there is silence”, 12.6.2). Our mind contains
“judging numbers” (internal principles of harmony), against which we
compare the “sensual numbers” (i.e. the harmonies we hear in the outside
world; n. 76 on p. 347). And these internal principles, since they
are unchanging and do not come from outside, must have been received from God (12.6.11).
• Everyone's mind is aware of certain universal principles of reasoning,
e.g. that the statement “if Plato runs, he moves” is true, regardless of
whether Plato happens to be moving right now or if he even exists or not; 12.7.5.
Such principles must come from God, since he is truth itself (12.7.6).
The book ends with another of those dodgy arguments for the immortality of the soul (12.7.13).
The soul is either the cause of its own existence, in which case it cannot perish;
or it comes from God, which is the same as the truth. The opposite of truth is
falsehood, which cannot kill the soul because falsehood “can do nothing further
but deceive; but unless someone is alive, he is not deceived”. And if not
even the opposite of truth can destroy the soul, then nothing can, so the soul
must be immortal.
Book XIII
This book tries to bolster the argument for the soul's immortality by showing
how the soul controls the body (rather than e.g. vice versa). Ficino gives
examples of how the emotions in our phantasy (desire, pleasure, fear, pain) influence
the body, e.g. fear makes us pale (13.1.1); a feeling of disgust provokes nausea (13.1.2).
Some of his examples are rather silly,
e.g. he suggests that a fetus is affected by “the greed of a pregnant woman”
or by “the vehemence of their [i.e. the parents'] phantasizing about the
various things that happen to affect them when they are mating!” (13.1.1)
Another example of the soul controlling the body is the ability of suitably stoical
philosophers or martyrs to bear pain with indifference (13.1.6).
Some philosophers (13.2.2) and priests (13.2.6) managed to withdraw from their
body for various periods of time during deep contemplation. Poets derive their abilities not from
training but from being seized by a divine frenzy (13.2.5). And the ability of prophets
to see the future comes from their soul detaching itself from the body, whereby it temporarily
reverts to its natural state of being present in every space and time (13.2.8).
Next Ficino describes a delightfully mystical theory of “three universal orders”.
First there is a hierarchy of minds, from god at the top, to angels and finally to minds of
rational souls. Rational principles emanate from god and descend down this hierarchy;
this “universal disposition [. . .] is called providence” (13.2.10).
Secondly, there is a hierarchy of rational souls, from the World-Soul down to the souls of the
twelve spheres and finally to the souls of individuals. In each soul there is a power
that provides life to its corresponding body; this power is called the “idolum” or
“simulacrum” (13.2.11). These idola are in a mutual accord, and seeds of corporeal
things descend down their hierarchy; “this concord, this transmission of seeds” is
fate (13.2.15).
Thirdly, there is a hierarchy of bodies, from the body of the world to the bodies of the
twelve spheres and finally to the bodies of individuals. The instincts of the higher natures
are transmitted down this hierarchy; this is called the natural order (13.2.16;
here “natures” = “complexions or affective dispositions”).
We are linked to all three orders: to providence through our mind (which is the highest
part of our soul), to fate through the idolum (which is the lowest power of the soul),
to nature through our body and its nature; but our reason, which is the middle part of our
soul, is not tied into any of these orders and can thus move the most freely (13.2.19).
Examples of how these links work: the minds above us send us an unexpected sudden insight
from time to time; our body may suddenly be affected by anxieties or mood swings and the like;
but our reason might or might not take notice of such influences, which shows that it's
independent of these links (13.2.20–2). The reason can notice these influences
better during periods of “emptying or release”: sleep, swoon,
solitude, etc. (13.2.24).
Another example of how our rational soul controls the body is the human ability to
learn various arts and skills, unlike e.g. animals, who have only a narrow range of
instinctive behaviours (13.3.1). Abilities such as acuity of mind, good memory,
prophecy, and a wide vocabulary (Ficino gives examples of each, mostly from ancient history),
also demonstrate the role of the soul as “God's emulator in the arts and governance”
(13.3.12), which shows its divine origin.
As another example of the soul's influence over bodies, not necessarily just its own
body, there's a hilarious explanation of how evil magic works: suppose a sorcerer wants
to give a child a fever; “[h]is imagining the fever arouses [. . .] his
choleric spirits”, which “in turn arouses [. . .] fetid and fever-causing
vapours [. . .] in the sorcerer's body [. . .] like arrows they speed
with the spirit to the spot the evil phantasy had intended as its mark”, especially
through the eyes (13.4.8). And more generally, we know that one soul can influence another
(e.g. by spreading vices), so it makes sense that it can also influence another's body,
since bodies are lower and weaker than souls (13.4.9).
Miracles can also be explained by a similar mechanism; the soul of someone who focuses
on the divine part of himself, on his mind, and disregards the senses, “emerges from
this body into the great [world] body, and, filled now with God, moves the humours of
this greater animal, the four elements, that is, of the greater world, as if they were
his own” (13.3.13). A man in this condition becomes pure mind, like an angel (13.3.12),
and is united with God (13.5.3). Sure it's nonsense, but it's beautiful, poetical nonsense.
Book XIV
Ficino discusses twelve properties of God and argues that our soul closely imitates
him in all those ways, and in fact strives to become God. But how will this striving
demonstrate the soul's immortality? Here he resorts to the good old argument from
incredulity: surely God wouldn't induce us to seek him in vain (14.1.5), so we will surely
become one with him one day and be immortal... (He makes arguments along similar lines
later too, e.g. in 14.2.10, 14.5.6.)
One thing I liked is that his twelve properties are not meant to be a specifically
christian thing: he says that “[i]n every nation all theology attributes these
twelve properties to God” (14.1.2).
• God is prime truth and prime good; and our soul desires truth and goodness
(14.2.2). And unlike most of our desires (e.g. for food and sex), this one is
insatiable (14.2.5).
• God is all things; and Ficino argues that our soul also tries to become all
things, as demonstrated by its various activities: sustaining the body, dealing with
senses, reasoning, investigating nature, contemplation of mathematics, inquiry into
divine mysteries (14.3.2). An even sillier argument comes later: “the intellect
seeks to understand all things” and understanding a thing, as we already saw
earlier (12.1–2), means taking the form of that thing, so our intellect seeks to become all
things (14.3.4).
• God is the author of all things and is above all. People take up various
arts and always strive to rule over others, so we are clearly imitating these properties
of God (14.4.2).
• God is everywhere and always, and man strives to be that too, e.g. by
exploring the universe and by striving for fame whereby posterity would remember him
(14.5.1–2). Besides, our soul has a natural desire for immortality (14.5.4).
• God is provident, just, steadfast, and temperate, four virtues which man
also strives towards (14.6.1). “Even thieves divide up their booty justly among
themselves”, and even evildoers often convince themselves that they are actually
behaving justly (14.6.3).
• “God's life is the most bountiful and the most delightful” (14.7.1), and
similarly our soul seeks riches and pleasure. As with many of these strivings to imitate
god, this can be done prudently or imprudently. A prudent man wishes to be rich in
understanding and virtue, an imprudent man in material goods, etc. (14.7.2).
I liked this argument: “[e]ach thing comes to rest [. . .] in its own
natural and habitual condition” (14.7.3), but man never quite knows rest while
he is alive, so clearly our natural condition is in the afterlife :)
• God “loves and worships Himself” (14.8.1), and so do people;
and, again, this ‘worshipping ourselves’ can be done prudently (and
result in e.g. a kind of modesty from not wishing to pollute one's mind) or imprudently
(stubbornness, arrogance etc.).
Furthermore, unlike lower animals, humans are naturally inclined towards religion and
the worship of God (14.8.3, 14.9.1); and this is universal across cultures (14.10.2, 10).
In fact Ficino says that religion comes so naturally to man that impiety is a kind
of aberration, a result of an imbalance in the humours (14.10.7); and
“generally the natural is true” (14.10.6). He uses this as an argument that
religion must be true, because it is natural; but surely this makes no more sense than
that old quip: ‘a billion flies can't be wrong — eat shit!’
There are a couple of hilarious arguments by wishful thinking.
You see, man would be very foolish if he put in all this effort into being religious
and didn't get immortality in return; but being so close to God, who is super wise,
makes it impossible that man would be so foolish; therefore he will get immortality in
return (14.7.8). :))))
And: “The probity of a truly pious man [. . .] strengthened by unvarying
habit is an indestructible good”, and thus deserves an indestructible reward,
i.e. immortality (14.10.14). And conversely, the impious soul “sins infinitely
whenever it forgets the infinite God”, so it needs to be immortal in order to
receive an appropriately infinite punishment (ibid.). Anything less than that
would be unjust.
*
Marsilio Ficino: Platonic Theology. Vol. 5: Books XV–XVI.
English translation by Michael J. B. Allen.
Latin text edited by James Hankins with William Bowen.
The I Tatti Renaissance Library, Vol. 17.
Harvard University Press, 2005.
0674017196.
vii + 353 pp.
Book XV
In this book, Ficino aims to refute Averroes' view that immortality of the soul does
not hold at the level of individuals but only for the human species as a whole. That is,
mankind as a whole has one intellect or mind in common, which is eternal;
but each individual man does not have an intellective soul of his own, but only a
sensitive one, which is born and dies together with his body (15.1.12). An individual man has
a cogitative soul which is capable of some quick and instinctive judgments, but real
understanding happens in the (common) mind (15.1.13), which is constantly being supplied by
images from the souls of individuals (15.1.15).
I liked the part where Ficino suggests that Averroes' mistakes are due to his studying
bad translations of Aristotle into Arabic :)) (15.1.2)
Many of Ficino's counterarguments revolve around the claim that the mind
is the “form of body”, and is therefore so closely
connected with the body that Averroes' view (that there is just one mind largely separate
from the individuals and their bodies) is untenable.
• We've already seen many times the Neoplatonic obsession with hierarchies,
and he presents several of them here, trying to argue that no matter how you look at this
“order of nature”, it requires the mind as the form of body (an intellectual form)
somewhere in the middle of his hierarchy. For example, there are forms which are divine
and cannot be united with matter; and there are forms which are natural and cannot be
separated from matter; so in between there need to be forms that partly divine, partly
natural, and can be united with matter but also separate from it (15.2.1).
Another such hierarchy: there must exist a pure good; an intellectual good and
pure intellect; an ensouled intellect and pure soul; and a corporeal soul. These four
levels correspond to God, angel, rational soul, and irrational soul (15.2.9).
God is not formed, does not form, and does not adhere to matter; angel is formed (by God),
does not form and does not adhere to matter; rational soul is formed, does form (the body),
and does not adhere to matter; and finally, the irrational soul is formed, does form and
does adhere to matter (15.2.11).
Another look at the same hierarchy: God is infinite with regard to being, essence and
power; angel is finite in being, but infinite in essence and power; the rational soul
is finite in being, but partly finite and partly infinite in essence and power; and finally
the corporeal form (irrational soul?) is finite in being, essence and power (15.2.14).
In short, for the hierarchy to work, you need the kind of rational soul that
Ficino has been describing throughout the Platonic Theology, and not
the kind of arrangement that had been described by Averroes.
The rational soul has to be incorruptible and joined to matter so that
it can exist as an intermediate level between angels (incorruptible and not
joined to matter) and the souls of beasts (corruptible and joined to matter);
15.4.4–5. He has a nice analogy about how soul is present in the body:
it fills it much like how sunlight fills the air, “one and undivided [. . .]
and the whole of it is in any part of the air” (15.5.4). In fact it's rather
the body that is in the soul than vice versa: “body is not present to all of
soul, but only to its lowest” part, i.e. the vital power, but not the power
of judgment, the higher part of soul, which is above the body (15.5.6).
• We say that man is a rational animal, but that wouldn't be true if all
mankind had just one mind in common, because then reason would be “extrinsic”
to man (15.6.1), being present only in that common mind. Similarly we say that man
understands things; but if Averroes' view were right, it would be only that common
mind that would understand anything (15.7.5). We say that a man can move himself
freely and make his choices, but under Averroes' view he would be moved by the
external mind, rather than freely moving himself (15.8.1).
• It is hard for us to focus on a bodily and a mental activity at the same
time: “guests are scarcely able to listen to the lyre and enjoy the meal at the
same time” (15.9.1). This sort of problem wouldn't occur if the mental activity
were coming from a universal human mind extrinsic to each individual.
• If Averroes' supposed common human mind really existed, it would be more
like heavenly minds, and wouldn't need to be connected to individual humans at all
and wouldn't need to receive images from them (15.10.1, 8). There would be no point
in the connection between such a common mind and an individual man; far from establishing
a new single composite thing, such a bond would be a “useless fabrication”
and a “monstrosity” (15.10.9).
• Ficino mentions an interesting distinction (which I think he hasn't mentioned
until now) between the “agent intellect” and the “receptive intellect”
(15.11.1); if I understand correctly, the difference is that species (= abstract concepts?)
are produced by the former and received by the latter. Under Averroes' view, the common
human mind is the agent intellect while individual humans have only a receptive intellect
(15.11.10), but Ficino argues that both the active and the receptive power are present
in each individual: the power of understanding must be present in an individual, otherwise
the universal mind wouldn't be able to make him understand things (15.11.11). (I must
admit that I still don't see why the receptive power shouldn't suffice for that, however.)
Sensing is the act of the body and soul together (as a composite), while
understanding is the act of the soul alone (15.12.10). We already saw that the
whole soul is present in each part of the body, but here we get an additional detail:
if e.g. a hand is amputated from the body, the soul instantly disappears from the
severed part (15.12.8).
• Having one mind per person, instead of one for the whole species, also
“contributes to their more perfect happiness” as they can “rejoice
together [. . .] in equal and mutual recognition and friendship”;
“the universe is far more beautiful if there is a multitude everywhere” (15.13.5).
I don't know that any of this constitutes an argument, but it's touching
and beautiful :)
• Ficino points out various more or less absurd consequences that would follow
from Averroes' theory that there is one mind common to all people. For example, every person
thinks that “I am one and the same person who is understanding
and perceiving” (15.14.2); but if Averroes's theory is right, the perceiving is
done by the individual person, but the understanding by the common human mind; and this mind
would presumable be aware of that fact, and would impart it to the individuals, so how
could everyone be mistaken about this?
Minds are receptive to truth,* and since so few people have been receptive to
Averroes' view of the one common human mind, this view is unlikely to be true (15.14.3).
[*This seems almost touchingly naive nowadays, when the internet is bursting
at the seams with conspiracy theories and disinformation... It is now clear that
minds are receptive to anything that looks vaguely truth-like and appeals to their
biases, whether it's true or not.]
“[O]n any given day innumerable men consider the same thing and are often
in error”, so if it's really Averroes' common human mind that's doing this understanding,
it follows that “that mind at any moment is considering the same thing thousands
of times over aand often being deceived” — an absurdity (15.15.5).
Another complication that would result from Averroes's common mind is what happens
if two people understand the same thing. Is (assuming that all the understanding is
being done by the common human mind) this one act of understanding or two,
and does it result in one species (= abstract concept) or two? Ficino finds all
possible answers to these questions unsatisfactory; and of course these problems do
not occur if you reject Averroes and allow the two people to have two separate minds (15.17.1).
If understanding is done by the common mind, “[h]ow then, when one person
ceases to understand, does another man not cease too?” (15.18.4) When a person
understands something, he is also aware that he understands this; and so “it is
beyond question amazing that the Averroistic mind which is single, eternal, indivisible,
uniform, and equally present to all, with you is aware of what it understands, but with
me is never aware of what it may understand in you” (15.18.8). And if all
understanding comes from the common mind, how can different people (e.g. different
philosophers) arrive at completely opposite opinions of the same question (15.19.3)?
• Ficino also says that the mind can preserve species (abstract ideas) and does
not need to have them constantly refreshed by images (15.16.3, 14). So Averroes' view of a common
human mind that is constantly being supplied with images from the souls of individual
people is unnecessary. In our phantasy, images sometimes spring up that it had never
received from the senses (15.16.11), which shows that it is rather the mind that supplies
the phantasy with images, not vice versa.
Book XVI
This book mostly deals with the question of why souls are imprisoned in such poor
earthly bodies, which if left unexplained could I guess be taken by some people as
throwing doubts on the view that the soul is of divine origin and hence immortal.
• Ficino says that such incarnation is desirable because it enables souls to
understand particular things instead of just abstract ideas. He describes how understanding
works at different levels of minds: at the top there's God, who understands everything
through one single Idea, “namely the one essence of God” (16.1.12) or
“the one Idea of being or the good, which Idea is God's nature itself” (16.1.14).
Then as you go lower through various levels of angelic minds, they understand things through
an increasingly large number of increasingly narrow Ideas: the one Idea splits into two
Ideas, of substance and of accident, and the highest angels understand things through
these two; lower down the Idea of substance separates into Ideas of corporeal and incorporeal
substance, the Idea of accident separates into Ideas of quality and quantity, etc. (16.1.15).
At the lowest level of minds, the human minds, ideas are split into those of individual
species, and this is what our minds understand (16.1.16).
Since our minds are the lowest
sort of minds, they are completely passive; they can receive these Ideas of species from
above, but can't apply them to the understanding of particular things belonging to such
species (16.1.17). For this we need reason, which works with the help of images coming from the
senses to gain an understanding of particular things, to “distribute the universal
Ideas of the mind into particular notions” (16.1.23); and for this our soul needs to
be in a body that is able to sense (16.1.19–20).
• Our souls are the lowest level that can deal with ideas; below that, they pass into
the material world and turn into mere “shadowy likenesses” of themselves
(16.3.1; an allusion to Plato's cave, I guess). But our soul can synthesize the perceptions
of these material things and abstract them back into Ideas again in our mind (16.3.2).
For Ficino, this ability is proof that our mind is much closer to the divine minds
above it than to bodies below, and is hence immortal.
• A rather unoriginal argument for incarnation: having to deal with the trouble
of being in a body will make our soul appreciate the “divine joys” (of a
bodiless existence) more... :S (16.4.1)
• Being in a body allows the soul to exercise its lower powers (phantasy,
sense, nutrition), which it otherwise would have no use for; but a limited time
suffices for this (i.e. it's OK if the body is mortal) “since the acts and
effects of these powers are wholly changeable and temporal”(16.5.1).
Besides our usual body, our soul also has an “ethereal body”, which
is immortal (16.5.4). Unlike some of the ancient Platonists, Ficino does not
seem to have believed in reincarnation, but he thought that the souls of the dead
can communicate with the living in visions and dreams (16.5.4–5).
He later adds that the soul enters the body out of a love for it, not due
to some sort of compulsion (16.7.14; I seem to vaguely remember reading the
same thing in Plotinus).
• Incarnation is a good thing because it makes the material world more similar to God,
by filling it with reason (because our souls have reason and are present in bodies); 16.6.1.
In fact each of the heavenly spheres also contains lots of souls.
Another potentially skeptical question that Ficino tries to address here is:
if souls are divine in origin, why are they afflicted by such tumultuous emotions?
He says it's because our body is “composed of four warring elements”,
it's constantly in some sort of flux and the soul is constantly busy trying to
preserve it (16.7.1). While doing so, it disturbs now this, now that humour
in our body, and images and emotions corresponding to that humour are awakened in us (16.7.11).
Furthermore, our body contains an “airy spirit” that can be moved by
the demons of the air, and this moves our humours too and excites emotions (16.7.18).
[I'm waiting with bated breath for the chapter about the water-demons that come up
the drainpipes, lurk in your toilet and... on second thought, never mind :)]
The souls in the heavenly spheres have an easier task because
they do not have to deal with any of this (16.7.4).
Lastly Ficino says a few words about the fear of death. This comes mostly from
the lower parts of the soul because they lose the body that they used to care for (16.8.2).
But “from the fear itself of death we can conclude that some sense will remain
in us after death” (16.8.8), otherwise there'd be nothing to fear about being dead.
Thus “if the dear of death originates from a horror of shadows, [our] immortality
is evidenced in this very fear” (16.8.8).
*
Marsilio Ficino: Platonic Theology. Vol. 6: Books XVII–XVIII.
English translation by Michael J. B. Allen.
Latin text edited by James Hankins with William Bowen.
The I Tatti Renaissance Library, Vol. 23.
Harvard University Press, 2006.
0674019865.
vii + 415 pp.
Book XVII
This book deals with the question of what is happening with the soul before
and after its sojourn in the body. I was under the impression that the usual christian
idea is that the soul is created at the time of conception or something like that;
well, ancient Platonists, it seems, often believed by contrast that the soul existed
before that and may have been subject to various kinds of transmigration. Ficino
begins with a nice little historical overview of where all this (neo)platonic
wharrgarble is coming from; he lists six principal ancient “theologians“:
Zoroaster,
Hermes Trismegistus,
Orpheus,
Aglaophemus, Pythagoras and Plato; and six ancient “academies” or schools of Platonism,
namely those of Xenocrates, Archesilas,
Carneades,
Ammonius,
Plotinus, and
Proclus (17.1.2).
As we've seen many times before, Ficino often relies heavily on the last two
of these (perhaps because their work has been better preserved than that of the
earlier Platonists?), though in the present book he'll have some cause to disagree
with them. He tells us that the ancient Platonists believed that the soul has always
existed, though if anything in his account is supposed to constitute an explanation
of why they thought so, I certainly have to admit that I couldn't understand it (17.2.5).
[Later he gives this rather feeble explanation: the soul has always existed,
“the Platonists say, because, unless it had no beginning, at some time it
would have an end”; 17.3.5. He himself condemns this idea in 17.4.4.]
He emphasizes the status of the soul as a “universal mean” (17.2.9)
between the indivisible minds above it and the entirely divisible qualities below it, etc.,
and says a little about the Pythagorean mysticism of numbers and harmonies with which
they described the soul — very poetic, but utterly insane (17.2.11–13).
There are several levels of souls: the divine or celestial souls (of the planetary
spheres and stars); angelic souls, demonic souls, heroic souls; and finally our human
souls at the lowest level, unless you want to also include the souls of beasts, which
are still further below us (17.2.15, 17.3.1). This brings us to one of the explanations
for reincarnation: unlike some of the higher sorts of souls, our poor lowly souls can't
simultaneously “use the human reason to gaze upon things divine and to govern
earthly bodies”, and “what they cannot do simultaneously they do in alternation”
(17.3.2), so they get incarnated for a time, then spend some time without a body between
two incarnations, and then get incarnated again and so on (17.3.5). The soul reincarnates
itself not by compulsion or deliberation, but by “a kind of natural instinct” (17.3.6),
and chooses its new life based on its habits and emotions from the previous one (17.3.8) —
which I guess is Plato's equivalent of karma :)
Over the course of these incarnations, the soul may travel up and down the levels,
living the angelic, demonic, heroic and human life; a more controversial
question was whether it could also get reincarnated in non-human animals. Plotinus
thought that it could, Proclus that it couldn't (17.3.10).
Ficino says (perhaps because all this reincarnation stuff is a little too
poorly compatible with christian religious beliefs?) that in these matters it
would be better to follow the earlier four schools of Platonism rather than these
last two (of Plotinus and Proclus), and that Plato's writings on this subject
were often meant to be understood poetically rather than literally, or that
they included things which he considered only probable rather than certain (17.4.1),
or that they were included only “for the sake of discussion” (17.4.14).
It's true, he says, that our soul cannot simultaneously govern our body and contemplate
the divine; but it doesn't have to handle this by reincarnation, it is enough simply to
do different things at different times in our life (17.4.2). Thus “a true
transmigration from species to species never occurs” (17.4.2),
and especially not from men to beasts (17.4.3–4). Ficino goes on to mention
many specific passages in Plato's works and discuss how they should be interpreted in this way.
So, no reincarnation for you!
Book XVIII
This book deals with miscellaneous questions and provides a sort of overview
of the lifecycle of the soul and its association with the body.
The (material) world cannot make or sustain itself (this would require the kind of
unity and infinite power which the body lacks due to its finite and divisible nature),
hence it must have been created (by God); 18.1.2. So it had to have a beginning,
and that was also the beginning of time: “[p]rior to the world's first moment
there were no other prior moments of time” (18.1.9). Ficino mentions some hilariously
specific ancient opinions about the precise moment of the world's beginning:
“Aries was in mid-heaven, Cancer was rising, the Moon was in Cancer, the Sun
in Leo” etc. etc. (18.1.12).
He presents an interesting hierarchy of spiritual beings with regard to duration
(18.2.1): God has no beginning and no end; spirits of beasts have a beginning and an end;
between them, occupying an intermediate position, angels and human souls have a beginning
but no end (i.e. they are immortal). The difference between angels and human souls
is that angels were born at the beginning of time, while human souls are born at various
later points (and on the other hand, the difference between angels and God is that the
latter exists outside of time altogether); 18.2.3.
Another good reason why our souls are created at the same time as our bodies:
if our soul had existed for some time before our body, it would like that kind of existence
so well that it would never choose to get incarnated :) (18.3.1).
Hence, new souls are being created every day — partly, it seems, simply
because creation is “God's principal activity” (18.3.13), so I guess
he just can't get tired of it.
Ficino discusses the opinions of ancient “theologians” about
where the soul comes from and how it enters the body, but distances himself from
these opinions, probably because the church might disagree with them
(18.5.4; “now and then, however, it is pleasant to converse with the ancients”,
18.4.1; “it is delightful to play poetically for a while with the ancients”,
18.5.1). There is, for example, the idea that to connect a simple and immortal spirit
(our soul) with a composite and mortal body (our material body), there needs to be something
intermediate: a simple and immortal body (18.4.1) — the “aethereal body received
from the aether” (18.4.3), which our soul receives first before entering our
material body. This aethereal body is the chariot from Plato's parable in the Phaedrus
(18.4.3). Some philosophers went further and said we have two simple bodies
(in addition to our usual, composite body, i.e. composed of the four elements),
an immaterial (celestial or aethereal) one and a material (airy) one (18.4.7).
There's also a chapter about where exactly in heaven the souls descend from:
“[p]rincipally from Cancer, according to the Platonists” (18.5.2),
though Ficino agrees that it would be silly to take this literally, and provides
a metaphorical interpretation. As the soul descends through the various heavenly (planetary)
spheres, it receives some character traits from each of them (18.5.2) and possibly
lives for some time on each sphere before descending further (18.5.3).
The soul is created and poured into the body 45 days after conception (18.6.1).
It enters the body through “the heart's midpoint, which is the
body's center” and thence diffuses through the body along with its natural heat (18.7.1).
After death, our soul, together with its aethereal body, returns “back to the aether”
(18.8.1); it is no longer influenced by living inside a body (symbolized by its bathing
in the river Lethe to purge itself of its memories), it can now live “in harmony
with the supercelestial gods”, i.e. the angels (18.8.6), and eventually merge itself
into God completely (18.8.7). How can our mind in that state understand God if he is
infinite? Well, partly the thing is that it doesn't understand all of him (18.8.22),
partly the light coming from him is poured into the mind and conveys some of his power
to it, thereby improving the mind's ability to understand him (18.8.21).
Since God himself is the cause of this union between a person's mind (in heaven)
and himself, nothing can dissolve it and the mind will remain unchanging (18.8.33–4).
In that state all people are content, as they find in God whatever it is that they
originally wanted in life — understanding, power, pleasure, etc. (18.8.35).
The blessed souls can be divided into nine levels, depending
on their attitudes towards divine goodness, power, and wisdom; and this division corresponds
to the different heavenly spheres and quite possibly to the angelic hierarchy as well (18.8.11–12).
There's an interesting chapter about what happens to the body after
death. We saw earlier that some of the ancient Platonists believed that
the soul eventually migrates to other bodies, possibly even those of
animals, and that Ficino largely disagreed with that. He points out that
the universe must eventually reach a static final state, because “rest
is more perfect than motion” (18.9.4). And in that perfect final
state, our souls must have bodies, because they have a sort of natural
inclination towards having a body and a state in which they have no body
would be imperfect (18.9.6–8); also, there should be a body to
share in the rewards or punishments of the soul (18.9.9). So they will
get a new body, which will be just like our original body (i.e. no
transmigration into a different body), in fact “rewoven”
or “reassembled” from the elements into which our original
body had been dissolved (18.9.10). The soul is the form of the body,
which is why the new body will be the same as the old one (because it
will be formed by the same soul; 18.9.10). However, this new body will
be perfect and immortal (nothing else would make sense in that perfect
end-state of the universe; 18.9.12).
Ficino also presents an interesting take on the fate of the soul in
the afterlife. I usually imagined these things as involving god judging
people and sending them to either heaven or hell, but here these things
are presented as a much more impersonal process. The rewards and punishments
in the afterlife are simply a continuation of the habits formed, and the
virtues and vices practiced, in the earthly life: “reward is virtue
fully grown [. . .] punishment is vice having reached maturity” (18.10.1).
During life, a man's phantasy processes images coming from the senses,
generates desires, etc.; but after death, having no body, these activities
end. Someone who lived virtuously and kept his phantasy under the control
of reason will find this to be a change for the better rather than for the worse
(his reason can contemplate divine things all the more easily now; 18.10.8),
but someone addicted to bodily pleasures will feel regret at their no longer
being available (18.10.10). If he was led in life by phantasy rather than
reason, the phantasy will now torment him after death by concocting
“gloomy images”, for want of having any real sense-perceptions
to process (18.10.14). Damned souls also suffer from their awareness of
being cut off from God (18.10.15). Ficino also cites various allegorical
interpretations of what the different parts of the ancient Greek underworld
stand for; not all the damned souls are equally bad there, and if their
vices weren't too habitual, they can eventually be purified of them (18.10.15).
Souls of those who died as “infants or idiots”, i.e. lacking
reason, cannot quite know and love God the way a normal soul would, and
thus cannot be completely blessed in the afterlife, but also do cannot do anything
to deserve to be condemned, and instead end up in a sort of intermediate state (18.11.1, 5),
though eventually even they may be turned towards full bliss (18.11.6–7).
Thus there is a hierarchy of four levels with regard to blessedness, from better to worse:
fully blessed souls; the intermediate state (partly blessed; infants and idiots);
souls that are still in bodies (not blessed but have hope for the future); and damned souls
(not blessed and have no hope); 18.11.2.
Ficino's Argument
As an appendix, vol. 6 also contains Ficino's ‘argument’
or introduction to the Platonic Theology, which he wrote shortly
before finishing the PT itself. The argument follows the structure
of the PT in its broadest outline but not necessarily in details.
Ficino divides it into “three steps of Platonic contemplation”.
The first step is the ascent to God, across the five levels of essence
(body, quality, soul, angel, God), which thus
corresponds roughly to book 1 of the PT. The second step
is the contemplation of God himself, i.e. a description of his various attributes,
which thus corresponds to book 2 of the PT. The third step
is the immortality of the soul, which thus corresponds to. . . books 3–18 of
the PT? You can see there's a certain lack of balance here :)
The section on the immortality of the soul here in the argument mostly
focuses on our capability for abstract thought, which (he says) demonstrates that our
soul can do something independent of the body and its sensations, and if it
can exist without the body then it must be immortal. But there are a great
many things in books 3–18 that are hardly even hinted at in this argument.
So as a sort of overall introduction to the work and to what it's trying to accomplish,
this argument isn't bad, but as a summary of the whole thing it leaves much to be desired.
But fortunately, vol. 6 also contains an “outline” or summary by
the translators (pp. 319–26), which is really excellent. It brings out
the internal structure of the Platonic Theology and covers all of its
parts; and it is, of course, infinitely better than my attempts to summarize it
in my blog post here.
There's also an interesting concordance table between the book and chapter numbers
of the present edition and the page numbers in the original publication of the
Platonic Theology in the 1576 edition of Ficino's collected works
(Opera). What impressed me is that the whole Platonic Theology
seems to cover only about 350 pages in that edition, so each page there must correspond
to about two pages in the ITRL edition. I guess it must be a huge folio
volume, like many in those days.
*
What to say at the end? Reading this was pretty hard work, and I'm glad that
I finally reached the end. Even though I was able to agree with almost nothing in Ficino's
book, I was happy enough to be impressed and charmed by the enormous castles in the sky
that he and the other Neoplatonists had built, and by his ingeniousness and subtlety
in coming up with endless numbers of arguments for the immortality of the soul.
At the same time I also couldn't help being a bit disappointed to see how easily
Ficino sometimes switches from the most sublime speculation about the highest principles
to the most credulous nonsense about astrology, demonic souls and the like.
How can it be that he and other Neoplatonists never at any point during the undoubtedly
long process of dreaming up their massive and complex system of thought took a moment
to pause and wonder: “Wait, how do we know if any of this is actually true?”
I can sort of understand that someone might, on the basis of abstract philosophical
arguments, convince himself about the existence of souls or of god and the like;
but when you start making ridiculously specific claims about the souls of the planets,
aerial and aethereal bodies, etc. — shouldn't you then pause and wonder whether
mere speculation can really prove that these specific claims (and not some other fairly
similar but still slightly different set of specific claims) are true? Ficino himself
often compares the opinions of various ancient philosophers about something and
points out their disagreements; if n people disagree, then at least
n − 1 of them are wrong; and isn't it then very plausible —
isn't it at least something you should seriously consider — that in fact all n
of them are wrong, and that none of them have the slightest clue about the subject
they're discussing?
Wouldn't it have been better simply to say ‘we have no idea’ instead
of spending what was probably years of work to write hundreds of pages of very cleverly
constructed arguments that are nonetheless utter nonsense from start to end?
Well, on second thought, perhaps it wouldn't have been. Ficino presumably liked
what he was doing, so it's hardly fair to say that he was wasting his time.
And we nowadays can at the very least marvel at his work, and no doubt some few
people — people quite unlike me — can also engage with it more productively.
So I guess I shouldn't complain after all. I don't mind his having written this book,
and I don't mind my having read it. If I had to summarize my impressions in
a single line, it would be the one from The Picture of Dorian Gray:
‘I didn't say I liked it. I said it fascinated me.’
Labels: books, I Tatti Renaissance Library, philosophy